Despite their elegant descriptions of animal behavior, I am
not sanguine about the effort of some scholars to extend consciousness to lower
animals like insects. One example of such efforts is found in the Nov./Dec. 2019
issue of American Scientist, by professors Chittka and Wilson. They
rightfully, I think, reject the possibility of consciousness in plants and
inanimate objects, because these have no agency; that is, they can’t move
around and do things. But the possession of agency is no assurance of consciousness.
Almost all animals exhibit agency, but how can we know that any non-human
species is conscious? In fact, many scholars are still debating the definition
of consciousness and nobody I know presumes to explain how the brain generates
consciousness.
The authors seem to confuse being awake with being
conscious. We humans are only conscious of those things to which our brain
attends, a well-documented phenomenon captured by the phrase “inattentional
blindness.” If you need convincing, see the classic video on U tube where a
gorilla walks through a basketball game and about 1/3 of the viewers fail to
see it.
Every consciousness theorist has the problem of finding a
good definition for consciousness. There is a solipsistic view that
consciousness is the only reality, that what we think we experience of the
world is an illusion created by consciousness. Few scientists take this view
seriously, because there is no evidence for this view.
Chittka and Wilson define consciousness as a kind of
thinking that allows avoidance of trial and error. That is not a sufficient
definition. A chain of stimuli can drive a chain of stereotyped behavioral
elements that produces adaptive behavior without the need for trial and error. I
have even published research on such behavior, the “flehmen” sexual behavior of
bulls, stallions, and males of certain other species. Chittka and Wilson use
the loaded term, “evaluate,” to say that is how bees plan the construction of a
hive and communicate to each other what to do. The claim is that they must be
conscious because hive building is not hardwired but has to be learned.
However, learning is also not an adequate criterion for consciousness:
computerized neural networks can learn, and few people would say that computers
are conscious beings.
Then, the authors argue that "self-recognition" is
a signature of consciousness. But "recognition" is not the same as
self-awareness. We humans have our body mapped in the sensory and motor
cortices, and the location of our body in space is mapped in the hippocampus-entorhinal
cortex. But these mappings can operate unconsciously. All of the behaviors of
bees, flies, and lower animals to which the authors ascribe consciousness can
be performed unconsciously as the nervous system reflexively responds to
environmental stimuli and feedback cues. Their use of descriptive words such as
"foresight, anticipation, communication, optimism/pessimism, appreciation,
picture (in the mind's eye)" are loaded anthropomorphic words used to
assume consciousness. Proof is lacking.
Finally, the authors say that neural correlates of
consciousness have not been identified in humans, but when they are, then
finding those correlates in lower animals would confirm that those species are
conscious. No, sorry, correlation is not the same as causation. Moreover, some
correlates of consciousness have been identified, as I describe in my book, Mental Biology.
Lorenz, Tinbergen, and von Frisch won the Nobel Prize in
1973 for showing that lower animals (including bees) can perform highly complex
behaviors in an automated way, without need for conscious "evaluation, foresight,
anticipation,” and so on. These founders of modern animal behavior should not
be dismissed by assigning consciousness to other species until we discover more
about the neural mechanisms of consciousness and whether a given species has
the neural resources to generate those mechanisms.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Please contribute your ideas. This blog is all about making learning easier for everyone.